Skip to content Skip to sidebar Skip to footer

what methods are used to interpret the constitution

Theories of Ramble Interpretation

The issue:  What are advisable sources of authority to guide interpretation of the Constitution and what relative weight should be assigned to the various appropriate sources?

Eight Reasons to exist an Originalist
1. Originalism reduces the likelihood that unelected judges will seize the reigns of ability from elected representatives.
two.  Originalism in the long run better preserves the authority of the Courtroom.
3.  Non-originalism allows too much room for judges to impose their own subjective and elitist values. Judges need neutral, objective criteria to make legitimate decisions.  The understanding of the framers and ratifiers of a constitutional clause provide those neutral criteria.
4. Lochner vs. New York (widely considered to be a bad non-originalist decision).
5.  Leaving it to the people to ameliorate their Constitution when need be promotes serious public fence about regime and its limitations.
6.  Originalism better respects the notion of the Constitution as a bounden contract.
7.  If a constitutional amendment passed today, we would expect a court v years from now to ask what we intended to adopt. [Tin can the same be said for a courtroom 100 or 200 years from now?]
8.  Originalism more often forces legislatures to reconsider and possibly repeal or amend their own bad laws, rather than to get out it to the courts to go rid of them.

.


.. Examples of Originalist Judges
Justice Hugo Black
Justice Antonin Scalia
Justice Clarence Thomas
Estimate Robert Bork

An Example of an Originalist Opinion:
Marsh vs Chambers


Robert Bork

Robert Bork Making the Case for Originalism:

If the Constitution is law, and then presumably its pregnant, like that of all other police, is the meaning the lawmakers were understood to accept intended.  If the Constitution is law, then presumably, like all other police, the significant the lawmakers intended is as bounden upon judges equally it is upon legislatures and executives.  There is no other sense in which the Constitution can be what article VI proclaims it to be: "Law...." This means, of course, that a estimate, no matter on what courtroom he sits, may never create new ramble rights or destroy sometime ones.  Whatsoever fourth dimension he does then, he violates not only the limits to his ain say-so only, and for that reason, also violates the rights of the legislature and the people....the philosophy of original understanding is thus a necessary inference from the structure of authorities apparent on the confront of the Constitution.
Introduction
In that location are five sources that have guided interpretation of the Constitution: (one) the text and construction of the Constitution, (ii) intentions of those who drafted, voted to propose, or voted to ratify the provision in question, (3) prior precedents (usually judicial), (4) the social, political, and economical consequences of alternative interpretations, and (5) natural law.  There is general agreement that the first three of these sources are advisable guides to interpretation, but considerable disagreement as to the relative weight that should be given to the iii sources when they signal in different directions.  Many interpreters of the Constitution accept suggested that the consequences of alternative interpretations are never relevant, fifty-fifty when all other considerations are evenly balanced.  Natural law (higher law, God'south police force) is at present but infrequently suggested equally an interpretive guide, even though many of the framers of the Constitution recognized its appropriateness.  Persons who favor heavy reliance on originalist sources (text and intentions) are usually called "originalists."  Persons who favor giving a more substantial weighting to precedent, consequences, or natural law are called "non-originalists."  In practise, disagreement betwixt originalists and not-originalists oftentimes concerns whether to apply heightened judicial scrutiny to sure "fundamental rights" that are not explicitly protected in the text of the Constitution.

Poll Question
To participate in the poll, go to this url:
world wide web.cali.org/instapoll


Definitions

Textualist: An originalist who gives chief weight to the text and structure of the Constitution.  Textualists oftentimes are skeptical of the ability of judges to determine commonage "intent."

Intentionalist: An originalist who gives primary weight to the intentions of framers, members of proposing bodies, and ratifiers.

Pragmatist: A not-originalist who gives substantial weight to judicial precedent or the consequences of alternative interpretations, and so as to sometimes favor a determination "wrong" on originalist terms because it promotes stability or in some other way promotes the public skilful.

Natural Constabulary Theorist: A person who believes that higher moral police ought to trump inconsistent positive police force.


Prof's Prerogative
Any theory of ramble theory that completely ignores consequences and focuses exclusively on text
     or original intentions is wrong.
.
        Any theory of ramble interpretation that completely ignores either text or original intentions and
     focuses primarily on consequences is wrong.
.
        Certain times and places are amend suited to one theory of constitutional interpretation than are other
     times and places.
.
        The Court should include justices with different approaches to constitutional interpretation.   A Court
     without dissenters is a Courtroom that volition not adequately inform us of the costs of choosing
the path taken.
2 SOCIETIES, Ii VIEWS
OF THE CONSTITUTION

American Constitution Gild

The Federalist Order

8 Reasons to be a Not-Originalist
one.  The framers at the Convention in Philadelphia indicated that they did non want their specific intentions to control interpretation.
2.  No written Constitution can conceptualize all the ways that government might in the future utilise to oppress people, so it is sometimes necessary for judges to fill in the gaps.
three.  Intentions of framers are various, sometimes transient, and often impossible to determine.  Text is often ambiguous and judicial precedents tin be found to support either side.  In such cases, why non produce the effect that volition best promote the public skilful?  Information technology'southward better than flipping a coin.
iv.  Non-originalism allows judges to head off the crises that could outcome from the inflexible interpretation of a provision in the Constitution that no longer serves its original purpose.  (The subpoena process is too difficult and cannot exist relied upon to save united states of america.)
5.  Non-originalism allows the Constitution to evolve to friction match more enlightened understandings on matters such equally the equal treatment of blacks, women, and other minorities.
half dozen. Brownish vs Board of Educational activity (on originalist grounds, it was decided incorrectly).
7.  Originalists lose sight of the forest because they pay besides much attention to copse.  The larger purpose--the animating spirit--of the Constitution was the protection of liberty, and nosotros ought to focus on that.
eight.  Nazi Frg: Originalist German language judges did non exercise the power they might accept to prevent or slow downwards inhumane programs.
Examples of  Non-Originalist Judges
Justice Harry Blackmun
Justice William Brennan
Justice William O. Douglas
Approximate Richard Posner


An Instance of a Non-Originalist Stance:
Griswold vs. Connecticut



Richard A. Posner

Approximate Richard Posner on the Importance of Judicial Gap-Filling:

A constitution that did not invalidate so offensive, oppressive, probably undemocratic, and sectarian law [as the Connecticut law banning the use or distribution of contraceptives] would stand up revealed equally containing major gaps.  Maybe that is the nature of our, or perhaps whatsoever, written Constitution; but yet, possibly the courts are authorized to plug at least the most glaring gaps.  Does anyone actually believe, in his eye of hearts, that the Constitution should be interpreted and so literally as to authorize every conceivable law that would not violate a specific constitutional clause?  This would hateful that a state could crave everyone to ally, or to have intercourse at to the lowest degree once a month, or information technology could take away every couple's 2d child and identify it in a foster dwelling....Nosotros find it reassuring to call back that the courts stand between us and legislative tyranny even if a particular form of tyranny was not foreseen and expressly forbidden by framers of the Constitution.

Further Reading

For another view: Strict Constructionism and the Strike Zone (1987, by Doug Linder)

Estimate Richard A. Posner on Originalism and Pragmatism
Excerpts from Overcoming Law (1995) ("What Am I?  A Potted Institute?" and "Bork and Beethoven")
Republished with permission of the author.

From "What Am I? A Potted Plant?"

*****Politically, I feel more governed than self-governing, and this is one reason why I call up more warmly of express government than of popular government. In considering whether to shrink what are now understood to be constitutional safeguards to the slight dimensions implied by a literal interpretation of the Constitution, nosotros should be careful to have a realistic, not an idealized, picture of the legislative and executive branches of government, which would be even more powerful than they are today if those safeguards were reduced.

The framers of a constitution who want to make it a charter of liberties and non just a prepare of constitutive rules confront a difficult choice.  They tin write specific provisions and thereby doom their work to rapid obsolescence, or they can write general provisions, thereby allowing substantial discretion to the authoritative interpreters, who in our system are the judges. The U.S. Constitution is a mixture of specific and general provisions. Many of the specific provisions have stood the test of time well or have been amended without much fuss. This is especially true of the rules establishing the structure and procedures of Congress. Most of the specific provisions creating rights, however, accept fared poorly. Some have proved irksomely anachronistic-for example, the right conferred by the Seventh Subpoena to a jury trial in federal in all cases at police force if the stakes exceed $20. Others have go dangerously anachronistic, such equally the right to bear arms. Some have turned topsy-turvy, such as the provision for indictment by grand jury. The grand jury has become an musical instrument of prosecutorial investigation on, rather than being the protection for the criminal suspect that the framers of the Pecker of Rights expected it to be.   If the Neb of Rights had consisted entirely of specific provisions, it would no longer be a significant constraint on the behavior of government officials.

Many provisions of the Constitution, however, are drafted in general terms.  This creates flexibility in the face of unforeseen changes, but information technology creates the possibility of alternative interpretations, and this possibility is an embarrassment for a theory of judicial legitimacy that denies judges accept whatsoever right to exercise discretion. A choice among semantically plausible interpretations of a text, in circumstances remote from those contemplated by its drafters, requires the exercise of discretion and the weighing of consequences. Reading is non a form of deduction; understanding requires a consideration of consequences. If I say, "I'll eat my chapeau," one reason why my listeners will "decode" the pregnant of this statement in nonliteral fashion is that I couldn't eat a chapeau if I tried. The broader principle, which applies to the Constitution equally much every bit to a spoken utterance, is that if ane possible interpretation of an ambiguous statement would entail absurd or terrible results, that is a good reason to reject information technology.

Even the conclusion to read the Constitution narrowly, and thereby to "restrain" judicial interpretation, is not a decision that can be read straight from the text. The Constitution does non say, "Read me broadly," or, "Read me narrowly." The decision to exercise one or the other must exist made as a matter of political theory and will depend on such things as one's view of the springs of judicial legitimacy and the relative competence of courts and legislatures in dealing with particular types of effect.

The Sixth Amendment provides that "in all criminal prosecutions, the defendant shall enjoy the right . . . to take the Assist of Counsel for his defense." Read narrowly, this just means that the accused can't be forbidden to retain counsel. If he cannot afford counsel, or competent counsel, he is out of luck. Read broadly, it guarantees fifty-fifty the indigent the effective aid of counsel. It becomes not just a negative correct to be allowed to hire a lawyer only a positive right to demand the help of the government in financing one's defense if ane cannot do it oneself. Either reading is compatible with the semantics of the provision, but the first ameliorate captures the specific intent of the framers. When the Sixth Amendment was written, English law forbade a criminal defendant to have the assistance of counsel unless his example presented abstruse questions of police. The framers wanted to exercise away with this prohibition. But, more broadly, they wanted to give criminal defendants protection against being railroaded. When they wrote, regime could not afford, or at least did not call back it could afford, to hire lawyers for indigent criminal defendants. Moreover, criminal trials were short and elementary, so it was not completely ridiculous to expect a lay person to exist able to defend himself competently from a criminal charge without a lawyer if he couldn't afford to hire i. Today the situation is different. Not but can the society afford to supply lawyers to poor people charged with crimes, but modern criminal law and procedure are then complicated that an unrepresented defendant is ordinarily at a great disadvantage.

***** The liberal judicial activists may be imprudent and misguided in their efforts to enact the liberal political agenda into constitutional law. But it is no use pretending that what they are doing is non estimation only "deconstruction," non police force only politics, only considering it involves the exercise of discretion and a concern with consequences and because it reaches results not foreseen two hundred years agone. It may be bad law considering information technology lacks business firm moorings in constitutional text, or structure, or history, or consensus, or other legitimate sources of ramble police, or because information technology is reckless of consequences, or because information technology oversimplifies difficult moral and political questions. Only information technology is non bad law, or no law, just because it violates the tenets of strict construction.

From "Bork and Beethoven"

The Tempting of America [by Judge Robert Bork] defends the position that "all that counts" to a judge interpreting the Constitution "is how the words used in the Constitution would have been understood at the time [of enactment]."  But rather than produce convincing reasons why society should want its judges to adopt originalism as their interpretive methodology in ramble cases, Bork seems nigh to want to place the issue outside the boundaries of rational debate. How else to explicate the pervasive religious imagery? It begins with the title of the book. Any doubtfulness that the reference is to the temptation is dispelled by the tide of the start chapter-"Creation and Fall"-which begins, "The Constitution was barely in identify when i Justice of the Supreme Courtroom cast covetous glances at the apple tree that would somewhen cause the fall."

*****A summons to holy war is not an argument for originalism. Bork'southward militance and dogmatism volition buck upward his followers and sweep forth some doubters, but it will not persuade neutrals. One specially wants a better ground than piety for genuflecting to originalism because Bork rightly if incongruously reminds u.s.a. of the danger of "absolutisms" and "abstract principles," criticizes reliance in constitutional law on "history and tradition," and implies in his interesting discussion of originalism'south historical roots that the nonoriginalist heresy may be function of the original 'understanding of the Constitution.

Bork thinks, originalism necessary in order to adjourn judicial discretion, and curbs on that discretion necessary in guild to keep the handful of unelected federal judges from seizing the reins of power from the people'south representatives. But if democracy is the end, originalism is a clumsy means. Bork notes that in the wake of the New Bargain the Supreme Court read out of the Constitution the limitations that the commerce clause of Article I appears to identify on the regulatory powers of the federal government. By the test of originalism, the Court erred. But by erring it transferred power to the people'south representatives.

And republic is not the end, at least not the unalloyed end. The democratic (really Bork means the populist) principle is diluted in our system of government. Policies are made by agents of the people rather than by the people themselves-precisely so that raw popular desire volition be buffered, civilized, guided, mediated by professionals and experts, informed through deliberation. Even the representatives do not accept a blank cheque. They are hemmed in by the Constitution itself representing, to be sure, popular preferences, but those of a sliver of a tiny population ii centuries ago. As Dworkin would say, the question posed by an originalist versus an activist or a pragmatist judiciary is not, one of democracy or no republic, only of the kind of commonwealth nosotros want.

*****Anyhow there is no evidence that the Court'southward authority depends on adherence to originalism.  Bork knows this, for he says (in great tension with his remark almost the destructibility of the institution) that "the Court is virtually invulnerable"; it "tin can practise what it wishes, and in that location is nearly no style to cease it, provided its result has a significant political constituency."  That is a sensible observation. The Court's survival and flourishing depend on the political acceptability of its results rather than on its adherence to an esoteric philosophy of interpretation. The Courtroom has never been consistently originalist, yet has survived. Maybe the Justices know more about survival than their critics do; we economist types believe that people generally know more than about how to protect their own interests than a kibitzer does.

Bork argues that if the only benchmark for evaluating the Supreme Court's decisions is their political soundness, anyone who thinks the Court is politically incorrect "is morally justified in evading its rulings whenever he can and overthrowing it if possible in lodge to supervene upon it with a trunk that will produce results he likes." He adds ominously: "The man who prefers results to processes has no reason to say that the Courtroom is more than legitimate than whatever other institution capable of wielding power. If the Court will not agree with him, why not argue his example to another grouping, say the Articulation Chiefs of Staff, a torso with rather better means for enforcing its decisions? No answer exists."

Really in that location are plenty of answers, and one is that Bork is posing a faux dichotomy: a courtroom committed to originalism versus a court that a "naked power organ;" blind obedience versus rebellion. These dichotomies imply, implausibly, that the only method of justification available to a courtroom, the only method of channeling judicial discretion and thus of distinguishing judges from legislators, is the originalist. No other method-one that emphasizes natural justice, sound justice, social welfare, or neutral (but not necessarily originalist) principles-so much equally exists. "The judge who looks outside the historic Constitution always looks inside himself and nowhere else."  And it may exist doubted whether the forbearance of the Joint Chiefs of Staff to endeavor a takeover of the government of the United States is dependent to the slightest degree on the Supreme Court'south adherence to originalism. If one may judge past the evidence that Bork arrays, the Courtroom has since the beginning strayed repeatedly from the originalist path, yet the Joint Chiefs (or their predecessors) have never tried to take over the authorities. Nor are they likely to endeavor.

*****The idea of the Constitution as a binding contract is an incomplete theory of political legitimacy, not an erroneous one. A contract induces, reliance that can make a potent merits for protection; it too frees people from having continually to reexamine and revise the terms of the relationship. These values are independent of whether the original contracting parties are still live. But a long-term contract is bound eventually to crave, if not formal modification (which in the example of the Constitution tin can be accomplished only through the amendment, process), then flexible interpretation, to cope finer with altered, circumstances. Modification and interpretation are reciprocal; the more difficult it is to modify the musical instrument formally, the more exigent is flexible interpretation. Bork is aware of the practical impediments to amending the Constitution but is unwilling to depict the inference that flexible estimation is therefore necessary to forestall constitutional obsolescence.

*****The long-expressionless framers are a convenient grouping to whom to laissez passer the buck. But although judges are not immune from the all too homo tendency to deny responsibleness for actions that cause pain, the significance of this fact is another affair. Information technology is a considerable paradox to advise that these reasons which uncandid judges requite for their actions are the only legitimate grounds for judicial action. If the result-oriented or activist judge is queasy about the championship deeds of his rulings, the originalist is (on the show of The Tempting of America, at any charge per unit) queasy about the consequences of originalist rulings. And rightly so. A theory of constitutional interpretation that ignores consequences is no more satisfactory than one that ignores the political importance of building a span between the contemporary approximate's pronouncement and some administrative document from the past. It is difficult to argue to Americans that in evaluating a political theory they should ignore its applied consequences. Bork is not prepared to make such an argument. He continually reassures the reader that originalism does not yield ghastly results, while at the same time denouncing judges who are "result-oriented."

*****The originalist faces backwards but steals frequent sideways glances at consequences. The pragmatist places the consequences of his decisions in the foreground. The pragmatist judge does not deny that his role in interpreting the Constitution is interpretive. He is not a lawless gauge. He does not, in guild to do short-sighted justice between the parties, violate the Constitution and his oath, for he is mindful of the systemic consequences of judicial lawlessness. Like Samuel Lipman'due south platonic usher, however, the pragmatist judge believes that constitutional estimation involves the empathic project of the judge's mind and talent into the creative souls of the framers rather than slavish obeisance to the framers' every metronome marking. In the capacious, frontwards-looking account of interpretation that I am calling pragmatic, the social consequences of alternative interpretations oftentimes are decisive; to the consistent originalist, if in that location were such a person, they would always be irrelevant.

In a representative republic, the fact that many (information technology need not exist most) people do not similar the probable consequences of a estimate'due south judicial philosophy provides permissible, and in any effect inevitable, grounds for the people's representatives to refuse to consent to his appointment, even if popular antipathy to the estimate is not grounded in a well-thought-out theory of adjudication.  The people are entitled to ask what the benefits to them of originalism would be, and they volition observe no answers in The Tempting of America.  If, to repeat Samuel Lipman again, orginalism make bad music despite or perhaps because of its scrupulous historicity, why should the people listen to it?

smartsopland.blogspot.com

Source: http://law2.umkc.edu/faculty/projects/ftrials/conlaw/interp.html#:~:text=Introduction%20There%20are%20five%20sources,the%20social%2C%20political%2C%20and%20economic

Post a Comment for "what methods are used to interpret the constitution"